lie-algebras-and-their-representations
Source code for my notes on representations of semisimple Lie algebras and Olivier Mathieu's classification of simple weight modules
Name | Size | Mode | |
.. | |||
sections/coherent-families.tex | 37169B | -rw-r--r-- |
001 002 003 004 005 006 007 008 009 010 011 012 013 014 015 016 017 018 019 020 021 022 023 024 025 026 027 028 029 030 031 032 033 034 035 036 037 038 039 040 041 042 043 044 045 046 047 048 049 050 051 052 053 054 055 056 057 058 059 060 061 062 063 064 065 066 067 068 069 070 071 072 073 074 075 076 077 078 079 080 081 082 083 084 085 086 087 088 089 090 091 092 093 094 095 096 097 098 099 100 101 102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 111 112 113 114 115 116 117 118 119 120 121 122 123 124 125 126 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135 136 137 138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148 149 150 151 152 153 154 155 156 157 158 159 160 161 162 163 164 165 166 167 168 169 170 171 172 173 174 175 176 177 178 179 180 181 182 183 184 185 186 187 188 189 190 191 192 193 194 195 196 197 198 199 200 201 202 203 204 205 206 207 208 209 210 211 212 213 214 215 216 217 218 219 220 221 222 223 224 225 226 227 228 229 230 231 232 233 234 235 236 237 238 239 240 241 242 243 244 245 246 247 248 249 250 251 252 253 254 255 256 257 258 259 260 261 262 263 264 265 266 267 268 269 270 271 272 273 274 275 276 277 278 279 280 281 282 283 284 285 286 287 288 289 290 291 292 293 294 295 296 297 298 299 300 301 302 303 304 305 306 307 308 309 310 311 312 313 314 315 316 317 318 319 320 321 322 323 324 325 326 327 328 329 330 331 332 333 334 335 336 337 338 339 340 341 342 343 344 345 346 347 348 349 350 351 352 353 354 355 356 357 358 359 360 361 362 363 364 365 366 367 368 369 370 371 372 373 374 375 376 377 378 379 380 381 382 383 384 385 386 387 388 389 390 391 392 393 394 395 396 397 398 399 400 401 402 403 404 405 406 407 408 409 410 411 412 413 414 415 416 417 418 419 420 421 422 423 424 425 426 427 428 429 430 431 432 433 434 435 436 437 438 439 440 441 442 443 444 445 446 447 448 449 450 451 452 453 454 455 456 457 458 459 460 461 462 463 464 465 466 467 468 469 470 471 472 473 474 475 476 477 478 479 480 481 482 483 484 485 486 487 488 489 490 491 492 493 494 495 496 497 498 499 500 501 502 503 504 505 506 507 508 509 510 511 512 513 514 515 516 517 518 519 520 521 522 523 524 525 526 527 528 529 530 531 532 533 534 535 536 537 538 539 540 541 542 543 544 545 546 547 548 549 550 551 552 553 554 555 556 557 558 559 560 561 562 563 564 565 566 567 568 569 570 571 572 573 574 575 576 577 578 579 580 581 582 583 584 585 586 587 588 589 590 591 592 593 594 595 596 597 598 599 600 601 602 603 604 605 606 607 608 609 610 611 612 613 614 615 616 617 618 619 620 621 622 623 624 625 626 627 628 629 630 631 632 633 634 635 636 637 638 639 640 641 642 643 644 645 646 647 648 649 650 651 652 653 654 655 656 657 658 659 660 661 662 663 664 665 666 667 668 669 670 671 672 673 674 675 676 677 678 679 680 681 682 683 684 685 686 687 688 689 690 691 692 693 694 695 696 697 698 699 700 701 702 703 704 705 706 707 708 709 710 711 712 713 714 715 716 717 718 719 720 721 722 723 724 725 726 727 728 729 730
\chapter{Classification of Coherent Families} % TODO: Write an introduction % TODOOO: Is this decomposition unique?? \begin{proposition} Suppose \(\mathfrak{g} = \mathfrak{s}_1 \oplus \cdots \oplus \mathfrak{s}_r\) and let \(\mathcal{M}\) be a semisimple irreducible coherent \(\mathfrak{g}\)-family. Then there are semisimple irreducible coherent \(\mathfrak{s}_i\)-families \(\mathcal{M}_i\) such that \[ \mathcal{M} \cong \mathcal{M}_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes \mathcal{M}_r \] \end{proposition} \begin{proof} Suppose \(\mathfrak{h}_i \subset \mathfrak{s}_i\) are Cartan subalgebras, \(\mathfrak{h} = \mathfrak{h}_1 \oplus \cdots \oplus \mathfrak{h}_r\) and \(d = \deg \mathcal{M}\). Let \(M \subset \mathcal{M}\) be any infinite-dimensional simple submodule, so that \(\mathcal{M}\) is a semisimple coherent extension of \(M\). By Example~\ref{thm:simple-weight-mod-is-tensor-prod}, there exists (unique) simple weight \(\mathfrak{s}_i\)-modules \(M_i\) such that \(M \cong M_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes M_r\). Take \(\mathcal{M}_i = \mExt(M_i)\). We will show that \(\mathcal{M}_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes \mathcal{M}_r\) is a coherent extension of \(M\). It is clear that \(\mathcal{M}_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes \mathcal{M}_r\) is a degree \(d\) bounded \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module containing \(M\) as a submodule. It thus suffices to show that \(\mathcal{M}\) is a coherent family. By Example~\ref{ex:supp-ess-of-tensor-is-product}, \(\operatorname{supp}_{\operatorname{ess}} (\mathcal{M}_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes \mathcal{M}_r) = \mathfrak{h}^*\). To see that the map \begin{align*} \mathfrak{h}^* & \to K \\ \lambda & \mapsto \operatorname{Tr} ( u\! \restriction_{(\mathcal{M}_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes \mathcal{M}_r)_\lambda} ) \end{align*} is polynomial, notice that the natural isomorphism of algebras \begin{align*} f : \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{s}_1) \otimes \cdots \otimes \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{s}_1) & \isoto \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g}) \\ u_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes u_r & \mapsto u_1 \cdots u_r \end{align*} described in Example~\ref{ex:univ-enveloping-of-sum-is-tensor} is a \(\mathfrak{g}\)-homomorphism between the tensor product of the adjoint \(\mathfrak{s}_i\)-modules \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{s}_i)\) and the adjoint \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\). Indeed, given \(X = X_1 + \cdots + X_r \in \mathfrak{g}\) with \(X_i \in \mathfrak{s}_i\) and \(u_i \in \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{s}_i)\), \[ \begin{split} f(X \cdot (u_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes u_r)) & = f([X_1, u_1] \otimes u_2 \otimes \cdots \otimes u_r) + \cdots + f(u_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes u_{r-1} \otimes [X_r, u_r]) \\ & = [X_1, u_1] u_2 \cdots u_r + \cdots + u_1 \cdots u_{r-1} [X_r, u_r] \\ \text{(\([X_i, u_j] = 0\) for \(i \ne j\))} & = [X_1, u_1u_2 \cdots u_r] + \cdots + [X_r, u_1 \cdots u_{r-1}u_r] \\ & = [X, f(u_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes u_r)] \end{split} \] Hence by Example~\ref{ex:adjoint-action-in-universal-enveloping-is-weight} \(f\) restricts to an isomorphism of algebras \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{s}_1)_0 \otimes \cdots \otimes \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{s}_r)_0 \isoto \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})_0\) with image \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})_0 = \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{s}_1)_0 \cdots \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{s}_r)_0\). More importantly, if we write \(\lambda = \lambda_1 + \cdots + \lambda_r\) for \(\lambda_i \in \mathfrak{h}_i^*\) it is clear from Example~\ref{ex:tensor-prod-of-weight-is-weight} that the \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})_0\)-module \((\mathcal{M}_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes \mathcal{M}_r)_\lambda\) corresponds to exactly the \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{s}_1)_0 \otimes \cdots \otimes \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{s}_r)_0\)-module \((\mathcal{M}_1)_{\lambda_1} \otimes \cdots \otimes (\mathcal{M}_r)_{\lambda_r}\), so we can see that the value \[ \operatorname{Tr} ( u_1 \cdots u_r \!\restriction_{(\mathcal{M}_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes \mathcal{M}_r)_\lambda} ) = \operatorname{Tr}(u_1\!\restriction_{(\mathcal{M}_1)_{\lambda_1}}) \cdots \operatorname{Tr}(u_r\!\restriction_{(\mathcal{M}_r)_{\lambda_r}}) \] varies polynomially with \(\lambda \in \mathfrak{h}^*\) for all \(u_i \in \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{s}_i)_0\). Finally, \(\mathcal{M}_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes \mathcal{M}_r\) is a coherent extension of \(M\). Since the \(\mathcal{M}_i = \mExt(M_i)\) are semisimple, so is \(\mathcal{M}_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes \mathcal{M}_r\). It thus follows from the uniqueness of semisimple coherent extensions that \(\mathcal{M} \cong \mathcal{M}_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes \mathcal{M}_r\). \end{proof} This last result allows us to concentrate on focus exclusive on classifying coherent \(\mathfrak{s}\)-families for the simple Lie algebras \(\mathfrak{s}\). In addition, it turns out that very few simple algebras admit irreducible coherent families at all. Namely\dots \begin{proposition}[Fernando]\label{thm:only-sl-n-sp-have-cuspidal} Let \(\mathfrak{s}\) be a finite-dimensional simple Lie algebra and suppose there exists a infinite-dimensional cuspidal \(\mathfrak{s}\)-module. Then \(\mathfrak{s} \cong \mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\) or \(\mathfrak{s} \cong \mathfrak{sp}_{2 n}(K)\) for some \(n\). \end{proposition} \begin{corollary} Let \(\mathfrak{s}\) be a finite-dimensional simple Lie algebra and suppose there exists an irreducible coherent \(\mathfrak{s}\)-family. Then \(\mathfrak{s} \cong \mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\) or \(\mathfrak{s} \cong \mathfrak{sp}_{2n}(K)\) for some \(n\). \end{corollary} The problem of classifying the semisimple irreducible coherent \(\mathfrak{g}\)-families for some arbitrary semisimple \(\mathfrak{g}\) can thus be reduced to a proof by exaustion: it suffices to classify coherent \(\mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\)-families and coherent \(\mathfrak{sp}_{2n}(K)\)-families. We will follow this path by analysing each case -- \(\mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\) and \(\mathfrak{sp}_{2n}(K)\) -- separately, classifying coherent families in terms of combinatorial invariants -- as does Mathieu in \cite[sec.~8,sec.~9]{mathieu}. Alternatively, Mathieu also provides a more explicit ``geometric'' construction of the coherent families for both \(\mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\) and \(\mathfrak{sp}_{2n}\) in sections 11 and 12 of his paper. Before we proceed to the individual case analysis, however, we would like discuss some further reductions to our general problem, the first of which is a crutial refinement to Proposition~\ref{thm:coherent-families-are-all-ext} due to Mathieu. % TODO: Note that we may take L(λ) with respect to any given basis % TODO: Note beforehand that the construction of Verma modules and the notions % of highest-weight modules in gerenal is relative on a choice of basis \begin{proposition}\label{coh-family-is-ext-l-lambda} Let \(\mathcal{M}\) be a semisimple irreducible coherent \(\mathfrak{g}\)-family. Then there exists some \(\lambda \in \mathfrak{h}^*\) such that \(L(\lambda)\) is bounded and \(\mathcal{M} \cong \mExt(L(\lambda))\). \end{proposition} \begin{note} I once had the opportunity to ask Olivier Mathieu himself how he first came across the notation of coherent families and what was his intuition behind it. Unfortunately, his responce was that he ``did not remember.'' However, Mathieu was able to tell me that ``the \emph{trick} is that I managed to show that they all come from simple highest-weight modules, which were already well understood.'' I personally find it likely that Mathieu first considered the idea of twisting \(L(\lambda)\) -- for \(\lambda\) with \(L(\lambda)\) bounded -- by a suitable automorphism \(\theta_\mu : \Sigma^{-1} \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g}) \isoto \Sigma^{-1} \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\), as in the proof of Proposition~\ref{thm:coh-ext-exists}, and only after decided to agregate this data in a coherent family by summing over the \(Q\)-cosets \(\mu + Q\), \(\mu \in \mathfrak{h}^*\). \end{note} In case the significance of Proposition~\ref{coh-family-is-ext-l-lambda} is unclear, the point is that it allows is to reduce the problem of classifying the coherent \(\mathfrak{g}\)-families to that of aswering the following two questions: \begin{enumerate} \item When is \(L(\lambda)\) bounded? \item Given \(\lambda, \mu \in \mathfrak{h}^*\) with \(L(\lambda)\) and \(L(\mu)\) bounded, when is \(\mExt(L(\lambda)) \cong \mExt(L(\mu))\)? \end{enumerate} These are the questions which we will attempt to answer for \(\mathfrak{g} = \mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\) and \(\mathfrak{g} = \mathfrak{sp}_{2n}(K)\). We begin by providing a partial answer to the second answer by introducing an invariant of coherent families, known as its \emph{central character}. To describe this invariant, we consider the Verma module \(M(\lambda) = \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g}) \cdot m^+\). Given \(\mu \in \mathfrak{h}^*\) and \(m \in M(\lambda)_\mu\), it is clear that \(u \cdot m \in M(\lambda)_\mu\) for all central \(u \in \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\). In particular, \(u \cdot m^+ \in M(\lambda)_\lambda = K m^+\) is a scalar multiple of \(m^+\) for all \(u \in Z(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g}))\), say \(\chi_\lambda(u) m^+\) for some \(\chi_\lambda(u) \in K\). More generally, if we take any \(m = v \cdot m^+ \in M(\lambda)\) we can see that \[ u \cdot m = v \cdot (u \cdot m^+) = \chi_\lambda(u) \, v \cdot m^+ = \chi_\lambda(u) m \] Since every highest-weight module is a quotient of a Verma module, it follows that \(u \in Z(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g}))\) acts on a highest-weight module \(M\) of highest-weight \(\lambda\) via multiplication by \(\chi_\lambda(u)\). In addition, it is clear that the function \(\chi_\lambda : Z(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})) \to K\) must be an algebra homomorphism. This leads us to the following definition. \begin{definition} Given a highest weight \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module \(M\) of highest weight \(\lambda\), the unique algebra homomorphism \(\chi_\lambda : Z(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})) \to K\) such that \(u \cdot m = \chi_\lambda(u) m\) for all \(m \in M\) and \(u \in Z(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g}))\) is called \emph{the central character of \(M\)} or \emph{the central character associated with the weight \(\lambda\)}. \end{definition} Since a simple highest-weight \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module is uniquelly determined by is highest-weight, it is clear that central characters are invariants of simple highest-weight modules. We should point out that these are far from perfect invariants, however. Namelly\dots % TODO: Cite the definition of the dot action \begin{theorem}[Harish-Chandra] Given \(\lambda, \mu \in \mathfrak{h}^*\), \(\chi_\lambda = \chi_\mu\) if, and only if \(\mu \in W \bullet \lambda\). \end{theorem} This and much more can be found in \cite[ch.~1]{humphreys-cat-o}. What is interesting about all this to us is that, as it turns out, central character are also invariants of coherent families. More specifically\dots \begin{proposition}\label{thm:coherent-family-has-uniq-central-char} Suppose \(\lambda, \mu \in \mathfrak{h}^*\) are such that \(L(\lambda)\) and \(L(\mu)\) are both bounded and \(\mExt(L(\lambda)) \cong \mExt(L(\mu))\). Then \(\chi_\lambda = \chi_\mu\). In particular, \(\mu \in W \bullet \lambda\). \end{proposition} \begin{proof} Fix \(u \in \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})_0\). It is clear that \(\operatorname{Tr}(u\!\restriction_{\mExt(L(\lambda))_\nu}) = \operatorname{Tr}(u\!\restriction_{L(\lambda)_\nu}) = d \chi_\lambda(u)\) for all \(\nu \in \operatorname{supp}_{\operatorname{ess}} L(\lambda)\). Since \(\operatorname{supp}_{\operatorname{ess}} L(\lambda)\) is Zariski-dense and the map \(\nu \mapsto \operatorname{Tr}(u\!\restriction_{\mExt(L(\lambda))_\nu})\) is polynomial, it follows that \(\operatorname{Tr}(u\!\restriction_{\mExt(L(\lambda))_\nu}) = d \chi_\lambda(u)\) for all \(\nu \in \mathfrak{h}^*\). But by the same token \[ d \chi_\lambda(u) = \operatorname{Tr}(u\!\restriction_{\mExt(L(\lambda))_\nu}) = \operatorname{Tr}(u\!\restriction_{\mExt(L(\mu))_\nu}) = d \chi_\mu(u) \] for any \(\nu \in \operatorname{supp}_{\operatorname{ess}} L(\mu)\) and thus \(\chi_\lambda(u) = \chi_\mu(u)\). \end{proof} Central characters may thus be used to distinguished between two semisimple irreducible coherent families. Unfortunately for us, as in the case of simple highest-weight modules, central characters are not perfect invariants of coherent families: there are non-isomorphic semisimple irreducible coherent families which share a common central character. Nevertheless, Mathieu was able to at least establish a somewhat \emph{precarious} version of the converse of Proposition~\ref{thm:coherent-family-has-uniq-central-char}. Namelly\dots \begin{lemma}\label{thm:lemma6.1} Let \(\beta \in \Sigma\) and \(\lambda \notin P^+\) be such that. \(L(\lambda)\) is bounded and \(\lambda(H_\beta) \notin \mathbb{N}\). Then \(L(\sigma_\beta \bullet \lambda) \subset \mExt(L(\lambda))\). In particular, if \(\sigma_\beta \bullet \lambda \notin P^+\) then \(L(\sigma_\beta)\) is a bounded infinite-dimensional \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module and \(\mExt(L(\sigma_\beta \bullet \lambda)) \cong \mExt(L(\lambda))\). \end{lemma} \begin{note} We should point out that, while it may very well be that \(\sigma_\beta \bullet \lambda \in P^+\), there is generally only a slight chance of such an event happening. Indeed, given \(\lambda \in \mathfrak{h}^*\), its orbit \(W \bullet \lambda\) meets \(P^+\) precisely once, so that the probability of \(\sigma_\beta \bullet \lambda \in P^+\) for some random \(\lambda \in \mathfrak{h}^*\) is only \(\sfrac{1}{|W \bullet \lambda|}\). With the odds stacked in our favor, we will later be able to exploit the second part of Lemma~\ref{thm:lemma6.1} without much difficulty! \end{note} While technical in nature, this lemma already allows us to classify all semisimple irreducible coherent \(\mathfrak{sl}_2(K)\)-families. % TODO: Add a diagram of the locus of weights λ such that L(λ) is % infinite-dimensional and bounded \begin{example} Let \(\mathfrak{g} = \mathfrak{sl}_2(K)\). It follows from Example~\ref{ex:sl2-verma} that \(M(\lambda)\) is a bounded \(\mathfrak{sl}_2(K)\) of degree \(1\), so that \(L(\lambda)\) is bounded -- with \(\deg L(\lambda) = 1\) -- for all \(\lambda \in K \cong \mathfrak{h}^*\). In addition, a simple calculation shows \(W \bullet \lambda = \{\lambda, - \lambda - 2\}\). This implies that if \(\lambda, \mu \notin P^+ = \mathbb{N}\) are such that \(\mExt(L(\lambda)) \cong \mExt(L(\mu))\) then \(\mu = \lambda\) or \(\mu = - \lambda - 2\). Finally, by Lemma~\ref{thm:lemma6.1} the converse also holds: if \(\lambda, - \lambda - 2 \notin P^+\) then \(\mExt(L(\lambda)) \cong \mExt(L(- \lambda - 2))\). \end{example} % TODO: Add a transition here \section{Coherent \(\mathfrak{sp}_{2n}(K)\)-families} % TODO: Fix n >= 2 Consider the Cartan subalgebra \(\mathfrak{h} \subset \mathfrak{sp}_{2n}(K)\) of diagonal matrices, as in Example~\ref{ex:cartan-of-sp}, and the basis \(\Sigma = \{\beta_1, \ldots, \beta_n\}\) for \(\Delta\) given by \(\beta_i = \epsilon_i - \epsilon_{i+1}\) for \(i < n\) and \(\beta_n = 2 \epsilon_n\). Here \(\epsilon_i : \mathfrak{h} \to K\) is the linear functional which yields the \(i\)-th entry of the diagonal of a given matrix, as described in Example~\ref{ex:sp-canonical-basis}. Also fix \(\rho = \sfrac{1}{2} \beta_1 + \cdots + \sfrac{1}{2} \beta_n\). % TODO: Add some comments on the proof of this: verifying that these conditions % are necessary is a purely combinatorial affair, while checking that these are % sufficient involves some analysis envolving the Shane-Weil module \begin{lemma}\label{thm:sp-bounded-weights} Then \(L(\lambda)\) is bounded if, and only if \begin{enumerate} \item \(\lambda(H_{\beta_i})\) is non-negative integer for all \(i \ne n\). \item \(\lambda(H_{\beta_n}) \in \frac{1}{2} + \mathbb{Z}\). \item \(\lambda(H_{\beta_{n - 1}} + 2 H_{\beta_n}) \ge -2\). \end{enumerate} \end{lemma} % TODO: Note that we need a better set of parameters to the space of weights % such that L(λ) is bounded % TODO: Revise the notation for this? I don't really like calling this % bijection m \begin{proposition}\label{thm:better-sp(2n)-parameters} The map \begin{align*} m : \mathfrak{h}^* & \to K^n \\ \lambda & \mapsto ( \kappa(\epsilon_1, \lambda+\rho), \ldots, \kappa(\epsilon_n, \lambda+\rho) ) \end{align*} is \(W\)-equivariant bijection, where the action \(W \cong S_n \ltimes (\mathbb{Z}/2\mathbb{Z})^n\) on \(\mathfrak{h}^*\) is given by the dot action and the action of \(W\) on \(K^n\) is given my permuting coordinates and multiplying them by \(\pm 1\). A weight \(\lambda \in \mathfrak{h}^*\) satisfies the conditions of Lemma~\ref{thm:sp-bounded-weights} if, and only if \(m(\lambda)_i \in \sfrac{1}{2} + \mathbb{Z}\) for all \(i\) and \(m(\lambda)_1 > m(\lambda)_2 > \cdots > m(\lambda)_{n - 1} > \pm m(\lambda)_n\). \end{proposition} \begin{proof} The fact \(m : \mathfrak{h}^* \to K^n\) is a bijection is clear from the fact that \(\{\epsilon_1, \ldots, \epsilon_n\}\) is an orthonormal basis for \(\mathfrak{h}^*\). Veryfying that \(L(\lambda)\) is bounded if, and only if \(m(\lambda)_1 > m(\lambda)_2 > \cdots > m(\lambda)_{n - 1} > \pm m(\lambda)_n\) is also a simple combinatorial affair. The only part of the statement worth proving is the fact that \(m\) is an equivariant map, which is equivalent to showing the map \begin{align*} \mathfrak{h}^* & \to K^n \\ \lambda & \mapsto (\kappa(\epsilon_1, \lambda), \ldots, \kappa(\epsilon_n, \lambda)) \end{align*} is equivariant with respect to the natural action of \(W\) on \(\mathfrak{h}^*\). But this also clear from the isomorphism \(W \cong S_n \ltimes (\mathbb{Z}/2\mathbb{Z})^n\), as described in Example~\ref{ex:sp-weyl-group}: \((\sigma_i, (\bar 0, \ldots, \bar 0)) = \sigma_{\beta_i}\) permutes \(\epsilon_i\) and \(\epsilon_{i + 1}\) for \(i < n\) and \((1, (\bar 0, \ldots, \bar 0, \bar 1)) = \sigma_{\beta_n}\) flips the sign of \(\epsilon_n\). Hence \(m(\sigma_{\beta_i} \cdot \epsilon_j) = \sigma_{\beta_i} \cdot m(\epsilon_j)\) for all \(i\) and \(j\). Since \(W\) is generated by the \(\sigma_{\beta_i}\), this implies that the required map is equivariant. \end{proof} \begin{definition} We denote by \(\mathscr{B}\) the set of the \(m \in (\sfrac{1}{2} + \mathbb{Z})^n\) such that \(m_1 > m_2 > \cdots > m_{n - 1} > \pm m_n\). We also consider the canonical partition \(\mathscr{B} = \mathscr{B}^+ \cup \mathscr{B}^-\) where \(\mathscr{B}^+ = \{ m \in \mathscr{B} : m_n > 0 \}\) and \(\mathscr{B}^- = \{ m \in \mathscr{B} : m_n < 0\}\). \end{definition} \begin{theorem}[Mathieu] Given \(\lambda\) and \(\mu\) satisfying the conditions of Lemma~\ref{thm:sp-bounded-weights}, \(\mExt(L(\lambda)) \cong \mExt(L(\mu))\) if, and only if \(m(\lambda)_i = m(\mu)_i\) for \(i < n\) and \(m(\lambda)_n = \pm m(\mu)_n\). In particular, the isomorphism classes of semisimple irreducible coherent \(\mathfrak{sp}_{2n}(K)\)-families are parameterized by \(\mathscr{B}^+\). \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let \(\lambda, \mu \notin P^+\) be such that \(L(\lambda)\) and \(L(\mu)\), so that \(m(\lambda), m(\mu) \in \mathscr{B}\). Suppose \(\mExt(L(\lambda)) \cong \mExt(L(\mu))\). By Proposition~\ref{thm:coherent-family-has-uniq-central-char}, \(\chi_\lambda = \chi_\mu\). It thus follows from the Harish-Chandra Theorem that \(\mu \in W \bullet \lambda\). Since \(m\) is equivariant, \(m(\mu) \in W \cdot m(\lambda)\). But the only elements in of \(\mathscr{B}\) in \(W \cdot m(\lambda)\) are \(m(\lambda)\) and \((m(\lambda)_1, m(\lambda)_2, \ldots, m(\lambda)_{n-1}, - m(\lambda)_n)\). Conversely, if \(m(\lambda)_i = m(\mu)_i\) for \(i < n\) and \(m(\mu)_n = - m(\lambda)_n\) then \(m(\mu) = \sigma_{\beta_n} \cdot m(\lambda)\) and \(\mu = \sigma_n \bullet \lambda\). Since \(m(\lambda) \in \mathscr{B}\), \(\lambda(H_{\beta_n}) \in \sfrac{1}{2} + \mathbb{Z}\) and thus \(\lambda(H_{\beta_n}) \notin \mathbb{N}\). Hence by Lemma~\ref{thm:lemma6.1} \(L(\mu) \subset \mExt(L(\lambda))\) and \(\mExt(L(\mu)) \cong \mExt(L(\lambda))\). For each semisimple irreducible coherent \(\mathfrak{sp}_{2n}(K)\)-family \(\mathcal{M}\) there is some \(m = m(\lambda) \in \mathscr{B}\) such that \(\mathcal{M} = \mExt(L(\lambda))\). The only other \(m' \in \mathscr{B}\) which generates the same coherent family as \(m\) is \(m' = \sigma_{\beta_n} \cdot m\). Since \(m\) and \(m'\) lie in different elements of the partition \(\mathscr{B} = \mathscr{B}^+ \cup \mathscr{B}^-\), the is a unique \(m'' = m(\nu) \in \mathscr{B}^+\) -- either \(m\) or \(m'\) -- such that \(\mathcal{M} \cong \mExt(L(\nu))\). \end{proof} \section{Coherent \(\mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\)-families} % TODO: Fix n >= 3 Consider the Cartan subalgebra \(\mathfrak{h} \subset \mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\) of diagonal matrices, as in Example~\ref{ex:cartan-of-sl}, and the basis \(\Sigma = \{\beta_1, \ldots, \beta_{n-1}\}\) for \(\Delta\) given by \(\beta_i = \epsilon_i - \epsilon_{i+1}\) for \(i < n\). Here \(\epsilon_i : \mathfrak{h} \to K\) is the linear functional which yields the \(i\)-th entry of the diagonal of a given matrix, as described in Example~\ref{ex:sl-canonical-basis}. Also fix \(\rho = \sfrac{1}{2} \beta_1 + \cdots + \sfrac{1}{2} \beta_{n - 1}\). % TODO: Add some comments on the proof of this: while the proof that these % conditions are necessary is a purely combinatorial affair, the proof of the % fact that conditions (ii) and (iii) imply L(λ) is bounded requires some % results on the connected components of of the graph 𝓑 (which we will only % state later down the line) \begin{lemma}\label{thm:sl-bounded-weights} Let \(\lambda \notin P^+\) and \(A(\lambda) = \{ i : \lambda(H_{\beta_i})\ \text{is \emph{not} a non-negative integer}\}\). Then \(L(\lambda)\) is bounded if, and only if one of the following assertions holds. \begin{enumerate} \item \(A(\lambda) = \{1\}\) or \(A(\lambda) = \{n - 1\}\). \item \(A(\lambda) = \{i\}\) for some \(1 < i < n - 1\) and \((\lambda + \rho)(H_{\beta_{i - 1}} + H_{\beta_i})\) or \((\lambda + \rho)(H_{\beta_i} + H_{\beta_{i + 1}})\) is a positive integer. \item \(A(\lambda) = \{i, i + 1\}\) for some \(1 \le i < n - 1\) and \((\lambda + \rho)(H_{\beta_i} + H_{\beta_{i + 1}})\) is a positive integer. \end{enumerate} \end{lemma} \begin{definition} A \emph{\(\mathfrak{sl}_n\)-sequence} \(m\) is a \(n\)-tuple \(m = (m_1, \ldots, m_n) \in K^n\) such that \(m_1 + \cdots + m_n = 0\). \end{definition} \begin{definition} A \(k\)-tuple \(m = (m_1, \ldots, m_k) \in K^k\) is called \emph{ordered} if \(m_i - m_{i + 1}\) is a positive integer for all \(i < k\). \end{definition} % TODO: Revise the notation for this? I don't really like calling this % bijection m \begin{proposition}\label{thm:better-sl(n)-parameters} The map \begin{align*} m : \mathfrak{h}^* & \to \{ \mathfrak{sl}_n\textrm{\normalfont-sequences} \} \\ \lambda & \mapsto 2n ( \kappa(\epsilon_1, \lambda + \rho), \ldots, \kappa(\epsilon_n, \lambda + \rho) ) \end{align*} is \(W\)-equivariant bijection, where the action \(W \cong S_n\) on \(\mathfrak{h}^*\) is given by the dot action and the action of \(W\) on the space of \(\mathfrak{sl}_n\)-sequences is given my permuting coordinates. A weight \(\lambda \in \mathfrak{h}^*\) satisfies the conditions of Lemma~\ref{thm:sl-bounded-weights} if, and only if \(m(\lambda)\) is \emph{not} ordered, but becomes ordered after removing one term. \end{proposition} % TODO: Note beforehand that κ(H_α, ⋅) is always a multiple of α. This is % perhaps better explained when defining H_α The proof of this result is very similar to that of Proposition~\ref{thm:better-sp(2n)-parameters} in spirit: the equivariance of the map \(m : \mathfrak{h}^* \to \{ \mathfrak{sl}_n\textrm{-sequences} \}\) follows from the nature of the isomorphism \(W \cong S_n\) as described in Example~\ref{ex:sl-weyl-group}, while the rest of the proof amounts to simple technical verifications. The number \(2 n\) is a normalization constant chosen because \(\lambda(H_\beta) = 2 n \, \kappa(\lambda, \beta)\) for all \(\lambda \in \mathfrak{h}^*\) and \(\beta \in \Sigma\). Hence \(m(\lambda)\) is uniquely characterized by the property that \((\lambda + \rho)(H_{\beta_i}) = m(\lambda)_i - m(\lambda)_{i+1}\) for all \(i\), which is relevant to the proof of the equivalence between the contiditions of Lemma~\ref{thm:sl-bounded-weights} and those explained in the last statement of Proposition~\ref{thm:better-sl(n)-parameters}. % TODO: Explain the significance of 𝓑 + and 𝓑 -: these are the subsets whose % union corresponds to condition (i) \begin{definition} We denote by \(\mathscr{B}\) the set of \(\mathfrak{sl}_n\)-sequences \(m\) which are \emph{not} ordered, but becomes ordered after removing one term. We also consider the \emph{extremal} subsets \(\mathscr{B}^+ = \{m \in \mathscr{B} : (\widehat{m_1}, m_2, \ldots, m_n) \ \text{is ordered}\}\) and \(\mathscr{B}^- = \{m \in \mathscr{B} : (m_1, \ldots, m_{n - 1}, \widehat{m_n}) \ \text{is ordered}\}\). \end{definition} % TODO: Add a picture of parts of 𝓑 for n = 3 in here % TODO: Explain that for each m ∈ 𝓑 there is a unique i such that so that % m_i - m_i+1 is not a positive integer. For m ∈ 𝓑 + this is i = 1, while for % m ∈ 𝓑 - this is i = n-1 The issue here is that the relationship between \(\lambda, \mu \in P^+\) with \(m(\lambda), m(\mu) \in \mathscr{B}\) and \(\mExt(L(\lambda)) \cong \mExt(L(\mu))\) is more complicated than in the case of \(\mathfrak{sp}_{2 n}(K)\). Nevertheless, Lemma~\ref{thm:lemma6.1} affords us a criteria for verifying that \(\mExt(L(\lambda)) \cong \mExt(L(\mu))\). For \(\sigma = \sigma_i\) and the weight \(\lambda + \rho\), the hypothesis of Lemma~\ref{thm:lemma6.1} translates to \(m(\lambda)_i - m(\lambda)_{i+1} = (\lambda + \rho)(H_{\beta_i}) \notin \mathbb{N}\). If \(m(\lambda) \in \mathscr{B}\), this is equivalent to requiring that \(m(\lambda)\) is not ordered, but becomes ordered after removing its \(i\)-th term. This discussions losely inspires the following definition, which endows the set \(\mathscr{B}\) with the structure of a directed graph. \begin{definition} Given \(m, m' \in \mathscr{B}\), say there is an arrow \(m \to m'\) if there some \(i\) such that \(m_i - m_{i + 1}\) is \emph{not} a positive integer and \(m' = \sigma_i \cdot m\). \end{definition} It should then be obvious from Lemma~\ref{thm:lemma6.1} that\dots \begin{proposition}\label{thm:arrow-implies-ext-eq} Let \(\lambda \notin P^+\) be such that \(L(\lambda)\) is bounded -- so that \(m(\lambda) \in \mathscr{B}\) -- and suppose that \(\mu \in \mathfrak{h}^*\) is such that \(m(\mu) \in \mathscr{B}\) and there is an arrow \(m(\lambda) \to m(\mu)\). Then \(L(\mu)\) is also bounded and \(\mExt(L(\mu)) \cong \mExt(L(\lambda))\). \end{proposition} A weight \(\lambda \in \mathfrak{h}^*\) is called \emph{regular} if \((\lambda + \rho)(H_\alpha) \ne 0\) for all \(\alpha \in \Delta\). In terms of \(\mathfrak{sl}_n\)-sequences, \(\lambda\) is regular if, and only if \(m(\lambda)_i \ne m(\lambda)_j\) for all \(i \ne j\). It thus makes sence to call a \(\mathfrak{sl}_n\)-sequence regular or singular if \(m_i \ne m_j\) for all \(i \ne j\) or \(m_i = m_j\) for some \(i \ne j\), respectively. Similarly, \(\lambda\) is integral if, and only if \(m(\lambda)_i - m(\lambda)_j \in \mathbb{Z}\) for all \(i\) and \(j\), so it makes sence to call a \(\mathfrak{sl}_n\)-sequence \(m\) integral if \(m_i - m_j \in \mathbb{Z}\) for all \(i\) and \(j\). % TODO: Restate the notation for σ_i beforehand \begin{lemma}\label{thm:connected-components-B-graph} The connected component of some \(m \in \mathscr{B}\) is given by the following. \begin{enumerate} \item If \(m\) is regular and integral then there exists\footnote{Notice that in this case $m' \notin \mathscr{B}$, however.} a unique ordered \(m' \in W \cdot m\), in which case the connected component of \(m\) is given by \[ \begin{tikzcd}[cramped, row sep=small] \sigma_1 \sigma_2 \cdots \sigma_i \cdot m' \rar & \sigma_2 \cdots \sigma_i \cdot m' \rar & \cdots \rar & \sigma_{i-1} \sigma_i \cdot m' \ar[rounded corners, to path={ -- ([xshift=4ex]\tikztostart.east) |- (X.center) \tikztonodes -| ([xshift=-4ex]\tikztotarget.west) -- (\tikztotarget)}]{dlll}[at end]{} \\ \sigma_i \cdot m' & \sigma_{i+1} \sigma_i \cdot m' \lar & \cdots \lar & \sigma_{n-1} \cdots \sigma_i \cdot m' \lar & \end{tikzcd} \] for some unique \(i\), with \(\sigma_1 \cdots \sigma_i \cdot m' \in \mathscr{B}^+\) and \(\sigma_{n-1} \cdots \sigma_i \cdot m' \in \mathscr{B}^-\). % TODOOO: What happens when i = 1?? Do we need to suppose i > 1? % TODO: For instance, consider m = (1, 1, -2) \item If \(m\) is singular then there exists unique \(m' \in W \cdot m\) and \(i\) such that \(m'_i = m'_{i + 1}\) and \((m_1', \cdots, m_{i-1}', \widehat{m_i'}, m_{i + 1}', \ldots, m_n')\) is ordered, in which case the connected component of \(m\) is given by \[ \begin{tikzcd}[cramped, row sep=small] \sigma_1 \sigma_2 \cdots \sigma_{i-1} \cdot m' \rar & \sigma_2 \cdots \sigma_{i-1} \cdot m' \rar & \cdots \rar & \sigma_{i-1} \cdot m' \ar[rounded corners, to path={ -- ([xshift=4ex]\tikztostart.east) |- (X.center) \tikztonodes -| ([xshift=-4ex]\tikztotarget.west) -- (\tikztotarget)}]{dlll}[at end]{} \\ m' & \sigma_{i+1} \cdot m' \lar & \cdots \lar & \sigma_{n-1} \cdots \sigma_{i+1} \cdot m' \lar & \end{tikzcd} \] with \(\sigma_1 \cdots \sigma_{i-1} \cdot m' \in \mathscr{B}^+\) and \(\sigma_{n-1} \cdots \sigma_{i+1} \cdot m' \in \mathscr{B}^-\). \item If \(m\) is non-integral then there exists unique \(m' \in W \cdot m\) with \(m' \in \mathscr{B}^+\), in which case the connected component of \(m\) is given by \[ \begin{tikzcd}[cramped] m' \rar & \sigma_1 \cdot m' \rar \lar & \sigma_2 \sigma_1 \cdot m' \rar \lar & \cdots \rar \lar & \sigma_{n-1} \cdots \sigma_1 \cdot m' \lar & \end{tikzcd} \] with \(\sigma_{n-1} \cdots \sigma_1 \cdot m' \in \mathscr{B}^-\). \end{enumerate} \end{lemma} % TODO: Notice that this gives us that if m(λ)∈ 𝓑 then L(λ) is bounded: for λ % ∈ 𝓑 + ∪ 𝓑 - we stablish this by hand, and for the general case it suffices to % notice that there is always some path μ → ... → λ with μ ∈ 𝓑 + ∪ 𝓑 - \begin{theorem}[Mathieu] Given \(\lambda, \mu \notin P^+\) with \(L(\lambda)\) and \(L(\mu)\) bounded, \(\mExt(L(\lambda)) \cong \mExt(L(\mu))\) if, and only if \(m(\lambda)\) and \(m(\mu)\) lie in the same connected component of \(\mathscr{B}\). In particular, the isomorphism classes of semisimple irreducible coherent \(\mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\)-families are parameterized by the set \(\pi_0(\mathscr{B})\) of the connected components of \(\mathscr{B}\), as well as by \(\mathscr{B}^+\). \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let \(\lambda, \mu \notin P^+\) be such that \(L(\lambda)\) and \(L(\mu)\), so that \(m(\lambda), m(\mu) \in \mathscr{B}\). It is clear from Proposition~\ref{thm:arrow-implies-ext-eq} that if \(m(\lambda)\) and \(m(\mu)\) lie in the same connected component of \(\mathscr{B}\) then \(\mExt(L(\lambda)) \cong \mExt(L(\mu))\). On the other hand, if \(\mExt(L(\lambda)) \cong \mExt(L(\mu))\) then \(\chi_\lambda = \chi_\mu\) and thus \(\mu \in W \bullet \lambda\). We now investigate which elements of \(W \bullet \lambda\) satisfy the conditions of Lemma~\ref{thm:sl-bounded-weights}. To do so, we describe the set \(\mathscr{B} \cap W \cdot m(\lambda)\). % Great migué If \(\lambda\) is regular and integral then the only permutations of \(m(\lambda)\) which lie in \(\mathscr{B}\) are \(\sigma_k \sigma_{k+1} \cdots \sigma_i \cdot m'\) for \(k \le i\) and \(\sigma_k \sigma_{k-1} \cdots \sigma_i \cdot m'\) for \(k \ge i\), where \(m'\) is the unique ordered element of \(W \cdot m(\lambda)\). Hence by Lemma~\ref{thm:connected-components-B-graph} \(\mathscr{B} \cap W \cdot m(\lambda)\) is the union of the connected components of the \(\sigma_i \cdot m'\) for \(i \le n\). On the other hand, if \(\lambda\) is singular or non-integral then the only permutations of \(m(\lambda)\) which lie in \(\mathscr{B}\) are the ones from the connected component of \(m(\lambda)\) in \(\mathscr{B}\), so that \(\mathscr{B} \cap W \cdot m(\lambda)\) is exactly the connected component of \(m(\lambda)\). In both cases, we can see that if \(B(\lambda)\) is the set of the \(m' = m(\mu) \in \mathscr{B}\) such that \(\mExt(L(\mu)) \cong \mExt(L(\lambda))\) then \(B(\lambda) \subset \mathscr{B} \cap W \cdot m(\lambda)\) is contain in a union of connected components of \(\mathscr{B}\) -- including that of \(m(\lambda)\) itself. We now claim that \(B(\lambda)\) is exactly the connected component of \(m(\lambda)\). This is already clear when \(\lambda\) is singular or non-integral, so we may assume that \(\lambda\) is regular and integral, in which case every other \(\mu \in W \bullet \lambda\) is regular and integral. % Great migué In this situation, \(m(\mu) \in \mathscr{B}^+\) implies \(\mu(H_{\beta_1}) = m(\mu)_1 - m(\mu)_2 \in \mathbb{Z}\) is negative. But it follows from Lemma~\ref{thm:lemma6.1} that for each \(\beta \in \Sigma\) there is at most one \(\mu \notin P^+\) with \(\mExt(L(\mu)) \cong \mExt(L(\lambda))\) such that \(\mu(H_\beta)\) is a negative integer -- see Lemma~6.5 of \cite{mathieu}. Hence there is at most one \(m' \in \mathscr{B}^+ \cap W \cdot m(\lambda)\). Since every connected component of \(\mathscr{B}\) meets \(\mathscr{B}^+\) -- see Lemma~\ref{thm:connected-components-B-graph} -- this implies \(B(\lambda)\) is precisely the connected component of \(m(\lambda)\). Another way of putting it is to say that \(\mExt(L(\lambda)) \cong \mExt(L(\mu))\) if, and only if \(m(\lambda)\) and \(m(\mu)\) lie in the same connected component -- which is, of course, precisely the first part of our theorem! There is thus a one-to-one correspondance between \(\pi_0(\mathscr{B})\) and the isomorphism classes of semisimple irreducible coherent \(\mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\)-families. Since every connected component of \(\mathscr{B}\) meets \(\mathscr{B}^+\) precisely once -- again, see Lemma~\ref{thm:connected-components-B-graph} -- we also get that such isomorphism classes are parameterized by \(\mathscr{B}^+\). \end{proof} % TODO: Change this % I don't really think these notes bring us to this conclusion % If anything, these notes really illustrate the incredible vastness of the % ocean of representation theory, how unknowable it is, and the remarkable % amount of engenuity required to explore it This construction also brings us full circle to the beginning of these notes, where we saw in Proposition~\ref{thm:geometric-realization-of-uni-env} that \(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules may be understood as geometric objects. In fact, throughout the previous four chapters we have seen a tremendous number of geometrically motivated examples, which further emphasizes the connection between representation theory and geometry. I would personally go as far as saying that the beautiful interplay between the algebraic and the geometric is precisely what makes representation theory such a fascinating and charming subject. Alas, our journey has come to an end. All it is left is to wonder at the beauty of Lie algebras and their representations. \label{end-47}