- Commit
- 04fa43522b0153f4f609d1909f2b9eaa8ba34532
- Parent
- a761a2d34aec5eb88048a4da38af7dc65ee6cd6e
- Author
- Pablo <pablo-escobar@riseup.net>
- Date
Added references to missing proofs
Also added a TODO item
Source code for my notes on representations of semisimple Lie algebras and Olivier Mathieu's classification of simple weight modules
Added references to missing proofs
Also added a TODO item
1 file changed, 22 insertions, 11 deletions
Status | File Name | N° Changes | Insertions | Deletions |
Modified | sections/mathieu.tex | 33 | 22 | 11 |
diff --git a/sections/mathieu.tex b/sections/mathieu.tex @@ -164,6 +164,7 @@ entire \(Q\)-coset it enhabits -- i.e. \(\operatorname{supp}_{\operatorname{ess}} K[x, x^{-1}] = 2 \mathbb{Z}\). This isn't always the case. Nevertheless, in general we find\dots +% TODOO: Explain what we mean by Zariski topology in 𝔥* \begin{proposition} Let \(V\) be an infinite-dimensional admissible representation of \(\mathfrak{g}\). The essential support @@ -171,11 +172,13 @@ isn't always the case. Nevertheless, in general we find\dots \(\mathfrak{h}^*\). \end{proposition} -Again, there is plenty of examples of completely reducible modules which are -\emph{not} weight modules. Nevertheless, weight modules constitute a large -class of representations and understanding them can give us a lot of insight -into the general case. Our goal is now classifying all irreducible weight -\(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules for some fixed reductive Lie algebra \(\mathfrak{g}\). +This proof was deemed too technical to be included in here, but see proposition +3.5 of \cite{mathieu}. Again, there is plenty of examples of completely +reducible modules which are \emph{not} weight modules. Nevertheless, weight +modules constitute a large class of representations and understanding them can +give us a lot of insight into the general case. Our goal is now classifying all +irreducible weight \(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules for some fixed reductive Lie +algebra \(\mathfrak{g}\). As a first approximation of a solution to our problem, we consider the induction functors \(\operatorname{Ind}_{\mathfrak{p}}^{\mathfrak{g}} : @@ -235,7 +238,7 @@ construction very similar to that of Verma modules. that Verma modules are indeed generalized Verma modules.}. \end{definition} -\begin{proposition} +\begin{proposition}\label{thm:generalized-verma-has-simple-quotient} Given an irreducible \(\mathfrak{p}\)-module \(V\), the generalized Verma module \(M_{\mathfrak{p}}(V)\) has a unique maximal subrepresentation \(N_{\mathfrak{p}}(V)\) and a unique irreducible quotient @@ -243,6 +246,8 @@ construction very similar to that of Verma modules. The irreducible quotient \(L_{\mathfrak{p}}(V)\) is a weight module. \end{proposition} +The proof of proposition~\ref{thm:generalized-verma-has-simple-quotient} is +entirely analogous to that of proposition~\ref{thm:max-verma-submod-is-weight}. This leads us to the following definitions. \begin{definition} @@ -544,7 +549,7 @@ to a completely reducible coherent extension of \(V\). % TODO: Note somewhere that M[mu] is a submodule % Mathieu's proof of this is somewhat profane, I don't think it's worth % including it in here -\begin{lemma} +\begin{lemma}\label{thm:component-coh-family-has-finite-length} Given a coherent family \(\mathcal{M}\) and \(\lambda \in \mathfrak{h}^*\), \(\mathcal{M}[\lambda]\) has finite length as a \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module. \end{lemma} @@ -647,7 +652,9 @@ to a completely reducible coherent extension of \(V\). In addition, there is no canonical choice of composition series. \end{note} -As promised, if \(\mathcal{M}\) is a coherent extension of \(V\) then so is +The proof of lemma~\ref{thm:component-coh-family-has-finite-length} is +extremily technical and may be found in \cite{mathieu} -- see lemma 3.3. As +promised, if \(\mathcal{M}\) is a coherent extension of \(V\) then so is \(\mathcal{M}^{\operatorname{ss}}\). \begin{proposition} @@ -748,7 +755,9 @@ coherent family are cuspidal representations? \(\mathcal{M}[\lambda] = V\) and \(\mathcal{M}[\lambda]\) is cuspidal. \end{proof} -To finish the proof, we now show\dots +Once more, the proof of proposition~\ref{thm:centralizer-multiplicity} wasn't +deemed informative enought to be included in here, but see the proof of lemma +2.3 of \cite{mathieu}. To finish the proof, we now show\dots \begin{lemma} Let \(\mathcal{M}\) be a coherent family. The set \(U = \{\lambda \in @@ -1042,8 +1051,10 @@ well-behaved. For example, we can show\dots functoriality of our constructions. \end{note} -Since \(F_\alpha\) is locally \(\operatorname{ad}\)-nilpotent for all \(\alpha -\in \Delta\), we can see\dots +The proof of the previous lemma is quite techinical and was deemed too tedious +to be included in here. See lemma 4.4 of \cite{mathieu} for a full proof. Since +\(F_\alpha\) is locally \(\operatorname{ad}\)-nilpotent for all \(\alpha \in +\Delta\), we can see\dots \begin{corollary} Let \(\Sigma\) be as in lemma~\ref{thm:nice-basis-for-inversion} and