lie-algebras-and-their-representations

Source code for my notes on representations of semisimple Lie algebras and Olivier Mathieu's classification of simple weight modules

Commit
1d71b805f37105f3a65c615550f3ad2fe849febb
Parent
d06a7808deb4c48b79fc009e855ef0d2405737ea
Author
Pablo <pablo-escobar@riseup.net>
Date

Switched the notation for completely reducible moddules

Replaced the term "completely reducible" by "semisimple"

Distinguished between the definition of "completely reducible modules" and that of "semisimple modules"

Diffstat

2 files changed, 79 insertions, 80 deletions

Status File Name N° Changes Insertions Deletions
Modified sections/complete-reducibility.tex 47 25 22
Modified sections/mathieu.tex 112 54 58
diff --git a/sections/complete-reducibility.tex b/sections/complete-reducibility.tex
@@ -97,21 +97,26 @@ impose on an algebra \(\mathfrak{g}\) under which every indecomposable
 theory as \emph{complete reducibility}.
 
 \begin{definition}
-  A \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module \(M\) is called \emph{completely reducible}, or
-  \emph{semisimple}, if it is the direct sum of simple \(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules.
+  A \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module \(M\) is called \emph{completely reducible} if
+  every \(\mathfrak{g}\)-submodule of \(M\) has a \(\mathfrak{g}\)-invariant
+  complement -- i.e. given \(N \subset M\), there is a submodule \(L \subset
+  M\) such that \(M = N \oplus L\).
 \end{definition}
 
-In case the relationship between complete reducibility and the simplicity of
-indecomposable \(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules is unclear, the following results
-should clear things up.
+\begin{definition}
+  A \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module \(M\) is called \emph{semisimple} if it is the
+  direct sum of simple \(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules.
+\end{definition}
+
+In case the relationship between complete reducibility, semisimplicity of
+\(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules and the simplicity of indecomposable modules is
+unclear, the following results should clear things up.
 
 \begin{proposition}\label{thm:complete-reducibility-equiv}
   The following conditions are equivalent.
   \begin{enumerate}
-    \item Every submodule of a finite-dimensional \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module has a
-      \(\mathfrak{g}\)-invariant complement -- i.e. given \(N \subset M\) there
-      is a \(\mathfrak{g}\)-submodule \(L \subset M\) such that \(M = N \oplus
-      L\).
+    \item Every submodule of a finite-dimensional \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module is
+      completely reducible.
 
     \item Every exact sequence of finite-dimensional \(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules
       splits.
@@ -119,8 +124,7 @@ should clear things up.
     \item Every indecomposable finite-dimensional \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module is
       simple.
 
-    \item Every finite-dimensional \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module is completely
-      reducible.
+    \item Every finite-dimensional \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module is simisimple.
   \end{enumerate}
 \end{proposition}
 
@@ -351,16 +355,15 @@ further ado, we may proceed to our\dots
 
 Let \(\mathfrak{g}\) be a finite-dimensional semisimple Lie algebra over \(K\).
 We want to establish that all finite-dimensional \(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules are
-completely reducible. Historically, this was first proved by Herman Weyl for
-\(K = \mathbb{C}\), using his knowledge of smooth representations of compact
-Lie groups. Namely, Weyl showed that any finite-dimensional semisimple complex
-Lie algebra is (isomorphic to) the complexification of the Lie algebra of a
-unique simply connected compact Lie group, known as its \emph{compact form}.
-Hence the category of the finite-dimensional modules of a given complex
-semisimple algebra is equivalent to that of the finite-dimensional smooth
-representations of its compact form, whose representations are known to be
-completely reducible because of Maschke's Theorem -- see \cite[ch.
-3]{serganova} for instance.
+semisimple. Historically, this was first proved by Herman Weyl for \(K =
+\mathbb{C}\), using his knowledge of smooth representations of compact Lie
+groups. Namely, Weyl showed that any finite-dimensional semisimple complex Lie
+algebra is (isomorphic to) the complexification of the Lie algebra of a unique
+simply connected compact Lie group, known as its \emph{compact form}. Hence the
+category of the finite-dimensional modules of a given complex semisimple
+algebra is equivalent to that of the finite-dimensional smooth representations
+of its compact form, whose representations are known to be completely reducible
+because of Maschke's Theorem -- see \cite[ch. 3]{serganova} for instance.
 
 This proof, however, is heavily reliant on the geometric structure of
 \(\mathbb{C}\). In other words, there is no hope for generalizing this for some
@@ -820,7 +823,7 @@ We are now finally ready to prove\dots
 
 \begin{theorem}
   Given a semisimple Lie algebra \(\mathfrak{g}\), every finite-dimensional
-  \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module is completely reducible.
+  \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module is semisimple.
 \end{theorem}
 
 \begin{proof}
diff --git a/sections/mathieu.tex b/sections/mathieu.tex
@@ -1,20 +1,19 @@
 \chapter{Simple Weight Modules}\label{ch:mathieu}
 
-In this chapter we will expand our results on finite-dimensional simple
-modules of semisimple Lie algebras by generalizing them on multiple
-directions. First, we will now consider reductive Lie algebras, which means we
-can no longer take complete reducibility for granted. Namely, we have seen that
-if \(\mathfrak{g}\) is \emph{not} semisimple there must be some
+In this chapter we will expand our results on finite-dimensional simple modules
+of semisimple Lie algebras by generalizing them on multiple directions. First,
+we will now consider reductive Lie algebras, which means we can no longer take
+the semisimplicity of modules for granted. Namely, we have seen that if
+\(\mathfrak{g}\) is \emph{not} semisimple there must be some
 \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module which is not the direct sum of simple
 \(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules.
 
-Nevertheless, completely reducible \(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules are a \emph{very}
-large class of representations, and understanding them can still give us a lot
-of information regarding our algebra and the category of its modules --
-granted, not \emph{all} of the information as in the semisimple case. For this
-reason, we will focus exclusively on the classification of completely reducible
-modules. Our strategy is, once again, to classify the simple
-\(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules.
+Nevertheless, semisimple \(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules are a \emph{very} large class
+of representations, and understanding them can still give us a lot of
+information regarding our algebra and the category of its modules -- granted,
+not \emph{all} of the information as in the semisimple case. For this reason,
+we will focus exclusively on the classification of semisimple modules. Our
+strategy is, once again, to classify the simple \(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules.
 
 Secondly, and this is more important, we now consider
 \emph{infinite-dimensional} \(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules too, which introduces
@@ -171,12 +170,11 @@ isn't always the case. Nevertheless, in general we find\dots
 \end{proposition}
 
 This proof was deemed too technical to be included in here, but see Proposition
-3.5 of \cite{mathieu}. Again, there is plenty of examples of completely
-reducible modules which are \emph{not} weight modules. Nevertheless, weight
-modules constitute a large class of representations and understanding them can
-give us a lot of insight into the general case. Our goal is now classifying all
-simple weight \(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules for some fixed reductive Lie algebra
-\(\mathfrak{g}\).
+3.5 of \cite{mathieu}. Again, there is plenty of examples of semisimple modules
+which are \emph{not} weight modules. Nevertheless, weight modules constitute a
+large class of representations and understanding them can give us a lot of
+insight into the general case. Our goal is now classifying all simple weight
+\(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules for some fixed reductive Lie algebra \(\mathfrak{g}\).
 
 As a first approximation of a solution to our problem, we consider the
 induction functors \(\operatorname{Ind}_{\mathfrak{p}}^{\mathfrak{g}} :
@@ -535,13 +533,12 @@ follows.
   for some \(\lambda \in \mathfrak{h}^*\).
 \end{definition}
 
-Another natural candidate for the role of ``nice extensions'' are the completely
-reducible coherent families -- i.e. families which are completely reducible as
+Another natural candidate for the role of ``nice extensions'' are the
+semisimple coherent families -- i.e. families which are semisimple as
 \(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules. These turn out to be very easy to produce. Namely,
-there is a construction, known as \emph{the semisimplification\footnote{Recall
-that a ``semisimple'' is a synonym for ``completely reducible'' in the context
-of modules.} of a coherent family}, which takes a coherent extension of \(M\)
-to a completely reducible coherent extension of \(M\).
+there is a construction, known as \emph{the semisimplification of a coherent
+family}, which takes a coherent extension of \(M\) to a semisimple coherent
+extension of \(M\).
 
 % Mathieu's proof of this is somewhat profane, I don't think it's worth
 % including it in here
@@ -552,9 +549,9 @@ to a completely reducible coherent extension of \(M\).
 
 \begin{corollary}
   Let \(\mathcal{M}\) be a coherent family of degree \(d\). There exists a
-  unique completely reducible coherent family
-  \(\mathcal{M}^{\operatorname{ss}}\) of degree \(d\) such that the composition
-  series of \(\mathcal{M}^{\operatorname{ss}}[\lambda]\) is the same as that of
+  unique semisimple coherent family \(\mathcal{M}^{\operatorname{ss}}\) of
+  degree \(d\) such that the composition series of
+  \(\mathcal{M}^{\operatorname{ss}}[\lambda]\) is the same as that of
   \(\mathcal{M}[\lambda]\) for all \(\lambda \in \mathfrak{h}^*\), called
   \emph{the semisimplification of \(\mathcal{M}\)}.
 
@@ -576,7 +573,7 @@ to a completely reducible coherent extension of \(M\).
 
 \begin{proof}
   The uniqueness of \(\mathcal{M}^{\operatorname{ss}}\) should be clear:
-  since \(\mathcal{M}^{\operatorname{ss}}\) is completely reducible, so is
+  since \(\mathcal{M}^{\operatorname{ss}}\) is semisimple, so is
   \(\mathcal{M}^{\operatorname{ss}}[\lambda]\). Hence by the Jordan-Hölder
   Theorem
   \[
@@ -591,7 +588,7 @@ to a completely reducible coherent extension of \(M\).
     = \bigoplus_{\substack{\lambda + Q \in \mfrac{\mathfrak{h}^*}{Q} \\ i}}
     \mfrac{\mathcal{M}_{\lambda i + 1}}{\mathcal{M}_{\lambda i}}
   \]
-  is indeed a completely reducible coherent family of degree \(d\).
+  is indeed a semisimple coherent family of degree \(d\).
 
   We know from examples~\ref{ex:submod-is-weight-mod} and
   \ref{ex:quotient-is-weight-mod} that each quotient
@@ -678,12 +675,12 @@ promised, if \(\mathcal{M}\) is a coherent extension of \(M\) then so is
 \end{proof}
 
 Given the uniqueness of the semisimplification, the semisimplification of any
-completely reducible coherent extension \(\mathcal{M}\) is \(\mathcal{M}\)
+semisimple coherent extension \(\mathcal{M}\) is \(\mathcal{M}\)
 itself and therefore\dots
 
 \begin{corollary}\label{thm:admissible-is-submod-of-extension}
   Let \(M\) be a simple admissible \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module and \(\mathcal{M}\)
-  be a completely reducible coherent extension of \(M\). Then \(M\) is
+  be a semisimple coherent extension of \(M\). Then \(M\) is
   contained in \(\mathcal{M}\).
 \end{corollary}
 
@@ -692,9 +689,8 @@ well behaved coherent extensions. A complementary question now is: which
 submodules of a \emph{nice} coherent family are cuspidal representations?
 
 \begin{proposition}\label{thm:centralizer-multiplicity}
-  Let \(M\) be a completely reducible weight \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module. Then
-  \(M_\lambda\) is a completely reducible
-  \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})_0\)-module for any \(\lambda \in
+  Let \(M\) be a semisimple weight \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module. Then \(M_\lambda\)
+  is a semisimple \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})_0\)-module for any \(\lambda \in
   \mathfrak{h}^*\), where \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})_0\) is the centralizer of
   \(\mathfrak{h}\) in \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\). Moreover, the multiplicity
   of a given simple \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module \(L\) coincides with the
@@ -880,11 +876,11 @@ coherent extensions, which will be the focus of our next section.
 
 \section{Localizations \& the Existence of Coherent Extensions}
 
-Let \(M\) be a simple admissible \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module of degree \(d\).
-Our goal is to prove that \(M\) has a (unique) irreducible completely reducible
-coherent extension \(\mathcal{M}\). Since \(M\) is simple, we know \(M
-\subset \mathcal{M}[\lambda]\) for any \(\lambda \in \operatorname{supp} M\).
-Our first task is constructing \(\mathcal{M}[\lambda]\). The issue here is that
+Let \(M\) be a simple admissible \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module of degree \(d\). Our
+goal is to prove that \(M\) has a (unique) irreducible semisimple coherent
+extension \(\mathcal{M}\). Since \(M\) is simple, we know \(M \subset
+\mathcal{M}[\lambda]\) for any \(\lambda \in \operatorname{supp} M\). Our first
+task is constructing \(\mathcal{M}[\lambda]\). The issue here is that
 \(\operatorname{supp}_{\operatorname{ess}} M\) may not be all of \(\lambda + Q
 = \operatorname{supp}_{\operatorname{ess}} \mathcal{M}[\lambda]\), so we may
 find \(M \subsetneq \mathcal{M}[\lambda]\). In fact, we may find
@@ -1333,10 +1329,10 @@ It should now be obvious\dots
 Lo and behold\dots
 
 \begin{theorem}[Mathieu]
-  There exists a unique completely reducible coherent extension \(\mExt(M)\) of
-  \(M\). More precisely, if \(\mathcal{M}\) is any coherent extension of \(M\),
-  then \(\mathcal{M}^{\operatorname{ss}} \cong \mExt(M)\). Furthermore,
-  \(\mExt(M)\) is a irreducible coherent family.
+  There exists a unique semisimple coherent extension \(\mExt(M)\) of \(M\).
+  More precisely, if \(\mathcal{M}\) is any coherent extension of \(M\), then
+  \(\mathcal{M}^{\operatorname{ss}} \cong \mExt(M)\). Furthermore, \(\mExt(M)\)
+  is a irreducible coherent family.
 \end{theorem}
 
 \begin{proof}
@@ -1353,10 +1349,10 @@ Lo and behold\dots
   M_\lambda\) is a simple \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})_0\)-module for some
   \(\lambda \in \operatorname{supp} M\).
 
-  As for the uniqueness of \(\mExt(M)\), fix some other completely reducible
-  coherent extension \(\mathcal{N}\) of \(M\). We claim that the multiplicity
-  of a given simple \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module \(L\) in \(\mathcal{N}\) is
-  determined by its \emph{trace function}
+  As for the uniqueness of \(\mExt(M)\), fix some other semisimple coherent
+  extension \(\mathcal{N}\) of \(M\). We claim that the multiplicity of a given
+  simple \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module \(L\) in \(\mathcal{N}\) is determined by its
+  \emph{trace function}
   \begin{align*}
     \mathfrak{h}^* \times \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})_0 &
     \to K \\
@@ -1365,8 +1361,8 @@ Lo and behold\dots
   \end{align*}
 
   It is a well known fact of the theory of modules that, given an associative
-  \(K\)-algebra \(A\), a finite-dimensional completely reducible \(A\)-module
-  \(L\) is determined, up to isomorphism, by its \emph{character}
+  \(K\)-algebra \(A\), a finite-dimensional semisimple \(A\)-module \(L\) is
+  determined, up to isomorphism, by its \emph{character}
   \begin{align*}
     \chi_L : A & \to     K                                    \\
              a & \mapsto \operatorname{Tr}(a\!\restriction_L)
@@ -1403,14 +1399,14 @@ Lo and behold\dots
 %  \(\operatorname{Ext}(M)\) are all the same.
 %\end{proposition}
 
-We have thus concluded our classification of cuspidal modules in terms
-of coherent families. Of course, to get an explicit construction of all
-simple \(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules we would have to classify the irreducible
-completely reducible coherent \(\mathfrak{g}\)-families themselves, which is
-the subject of sections 7, 8 and 9 of \cite{mathieu}. In addition, in sections
-11 and 12 of \cite{mathieu} Mathieu provides an explicit construction of
-coherent families. We unfortunately do not have the necessary space to discuss
-these results in detail, but we will now provide a brief overview.
+We have thus concluded our classification of cuspidal modules in terms of
+coherent families. Of course, to get an explicit construction of all simple
+\(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules we would have to classify the irreducible semisimple
+coherent \(\mathfrak{g}\)-families themselves, which is the subject of sections
+7, 8 and 9 of \cite{mathieu}. In addition, in sections 11 and 12 of
+\cite{mathieu} Mathieu provides an explicit construction of coherent families.
+We unfortunately do not have the necessary space to discuss these results in
+detail, but we will now provide a brief overview.
 
 First and foremost, the problem of classifying \(\mathfrak{g}\)-family can be
 reduced to that of classifying only \(\mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\)-families and
@@ -1446,7 +1442,7 @@ and \(\mathfrak{sp}_{2 n}(K)\) admit cuspidal modules, so it suffices to
 consider these two cases.
 
 Finally, we apply Mathieu's results to further reduce the problem to that of
-classifying the irreducible completely reducible coherent families of
+classifying the irreducible semisimple coherent families of
 \(\mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\) and \(\mathfrak{sp}_{2 n}(K)\). These can be described
 either algebraically, using combinatorial invariants -- which Mathieu does in
 sections 7, 8 and 9 of his paper -- or geometrically, using algebraic varieties