- Commit
- 6002e16967e2554dbb16382c17b8a9fb767bbbb9
- Parent
- 62ebb3219195eb47aaeb7118688a0fd63e523ee0
- Author
- Pablo <pablo-escobar@riseup.net>
- Date
Revised the first chapter (again)
Implemented Kashuba's suggestions
Source code for my notes on representations of semisimple Lie algebras and Olivier Mathieu's classification of simple weight modules
Revised the first chapter (again)
Implemented Kashuba's suggestions
1 file changed, 42 insertions, 43 deletions
Status | File Name | N° Changes | Insertions | Deletions |
Modified | sections/introduction.tex | 85 | 42 | 43 |
diff --git a/sections/introduction.tex b/sections/introduction.tex @@ -226,20 +226,20 @@ invariants. Even more so\dots This last theorem is a direct corollary of the so called \emph{first and third fundamental Lie theorems}. Lie's first theorem establishes that if \(G\) is a -simply connected Lie group and \(H\) is connected then the induced map -\(\operatorname{Hom}(G, H) \to \operatorname{Hom}(\mathfrak{g}, \mathfrak{h})\) -is bijective, which implies the Lie functor is fully faithful. On the -other hand, Lie's third theorem states every finite-dimensional real Lie -algebra is the Lie algebra of a simply connected Lie group -- i.e. the Lie -functor is essentially surjective. +simply connected Lie group and \(H\) is a connected Lie group then the induced +map \(\operatorname{Hom}(G, H) \to \operatorname{Hom}(\mathfrak{g}, +\mathfrak{h})\) is bijective, which implies the Lie functor is fully faithful. +On the other hand, Lie's third theorem states that every finite-dimensional +real Lie algebra is the Lie algebra of a simply connected Lie group -- i.e. the +Lie functor is essentially surjective. This goes to show that the relationship between Lie groups and Lie algebras is deeper than the fact they share a name: in a very strong sense, studying simply connected Lie groups is \emph{precisely} the same as studying finite-dimensional Lie algebras. Such a vital connection between apparently distant subjects is bound to produce interesting results. Indeed, the passage -from the algebraic and the geometric and vice-versa has proven itself a -fruitful one. +from the geometric setting to its algebraic counterpart and vice-versa has +proven itself a fruitful one. This correspondence can be extended to the complex case too. In other words, the Lie functor \(\mathbf{CLieGrp}_{\operatorname{simpl}} \to @@ -270,7 +270,7 @@ can be complicated beasts themselves. They are, after all, nonlinear objects. On the other hand, Lie algebras are linear by nature, which makes them much more flexible than groups. -Having thus hopefully established Lie algebras are interesting, we are now +Having thus hopefully established that Lie algebras are interesting, we are now ready to dive deeper into them. We begin by analyzing some of their most basic properties. @@ -352,14 +352,17 @@ There is also a natural analogue of quotients. \end{center} \end{proposition} -Due to their relationship with Lie groups and algebraic groups, Lie algebras -also share structural features with groups. For example\dots - \begin{definition} A Lie algebra \(\mathfrak{g}\) is called \emph{Abelian} if \([X, Y] = 0\) for all \(X, Y \in \mathfrak{g}\). \end{definition} +\begin{example} + Let \(G\) be a connected algebraic \(K\)-group and \(\mathfrak{g}\) be its + Lie algebra. Then \(G\) is Abelian if, and only if \(\mathfrak{g}\) is + Abelian. +\end{example} + \begin{note} Notice that an Abelian Lie algebra is determined by its dimension. Indeed, any linear map \(\mathfrak{g} \to \mathfrak{h}\) between Abelian Lie algebras @@ -370,18 +373,15 @@ also share structural features with groups. For example\dots \end{note} \begin{example} - Let \(G\) be a connected algebraic \(K\)-group and \(\mathfrak{g}\) be its - Lie algebra. Then \(G\) is Abelian if, and only if \(\mathfrak{g}\) is - Abelian. -\end{example} - -\begin{example} Let \(\mathfrak{g}\) be a Lie algebra and \(\mathfrak{z} = \{ X \in \mathfrak{g} : [X, Y] = 0 \; \forall Y \in \mathfrak{g}\}\). Then \(\mathfrak{z}\) is an Abelian ideal of \(\mathfrak{g}\), known as \emph{the center of \(\mathfrak{z}\)}. \end{example} +Due to their relationship with Lie groups and algebraic groups, Lie algebras +also share structural features with groups. For example\dots + \begin{definition} A Lie algebra \(\mathfrak{g}\) is called \emph{solvable} if its derived series @@ -541,10 +541,9 @@ associative algebra, known as \emph{the universal enveloping algebra of \mathfrak{g}^{\otimes n}\) be its tensor algebra -- i.e. the free \(K\)-algebra generated by the elements of \(\mathfrak{g}\). We call the \(K\)-algebra \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g}) = \mfrac{T \mathfrak{g}}{I}\) - \emph{the universal enveloping algebra of \(\mathfrak{g}\)}, where \(I = ([X, - Y] - (X \otimes Y - Y \otimes X) : X, Y \in \mathfrak{g})\) is the left ideal - of \(T \mathfrak{g}\) generated by the elements \([X, Y] - (X \otimes Y - Y - \otimes X)\). + \emph{the universal enveloping algebra of \(\mathfrak{g}\)}, where \(I\) is + the left ideal of \(T \mathfrak{g}\) generated by the elements \([X, Y] - (X + \otimes Y - Y \otimes X)\). \end{definition} Notice there is a canonical homomorphism \(\mathfrak{g} \to @@ -557,15 +556,15 @@ Notice there is a canonical homomorphism \(\mathfrak{g} \to \end{tikzcd} \end{center} -Given \(X_1, \ldots, X_n \in \mathfrak{g}\), we denote the image of \(X_i\) -under the inclusion \(\mathfrak{g} \to T \mathfrak{g}\) simply by \(X_i\) and -we write \(X_1 \cdots X_n\) for \((X_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes X_n) + I\). This -notation suggests the map \(\mathfrak{g} \to \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\) is -injective, but at this point this is not at all clear -- given that the -projection \(T \mathfrak{g} \to \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\) is not injective. -However, we will soon see this is the case. Intuitively, -\(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\) is the smallest associative \(K\)-algebra -containing \(\mathfrak{g}\) as a Lie subalgebra. In practice this means\dots +Given \(X_1, \ldots, X_n \in \mathfrak{g}\), we identify \(X_i\) with its image +under the inclusion \(\mathfrak{g} \to T \mathfrak{g}\) and we write \(X_1 +\cdots X_n\) for \((X_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes X_n) + I\). This notation +suggests the map \(\mathfrak{g} \to \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\) is injective, +but at this point this is not at all clear -- given that the projection \(T +\mathfrak{g} \to \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\) is not injective. However, we will +soon see this is the case. Intuitively, \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\) is the +smallest associative \(K\)-algebra containing \(\mathfrak{g}\) as a Lie +subalgebra. In practice this means\dots \begin{proposition}\label{thm:universal-env-uni-prop} Let \(\mathfrak{g}\) be a Lie algebra and \(A\) be an associative @@ -742,7 +741,8 @@ over the ring of \(G\)-invariant differential operators -- i.e. Proposition~\ref{thm:geometric-realization-of-uni-env} is in fact only the beginning of a profound connection between the theory of \(D\)-modules and and -\emph{representation theory}, which we will explore in the next section. +\emph{representation theory}, the latter of which we now explore in the +following section. \section{Representation Theory} @@ -776,6 +776,9 @@ definition. \mathfrak{gl}(V)\). \end{definition} +Hence there is a one-to-one correspondence between representations of +\(\mathfrak{g}\) and \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\)-modules. + \begin{example} Given a Lie algebra \(\mathfrak{g}\), the zero map \(0 : \mathfrak{g} \to K\) gives \(K\) the structure of a representation of \(\mathfrak{g}\), known as @@ -797,10 +800,9 @@ definition. representation of \(\mathfrak{g}\)}. \end{example} -Hence there is a one-to-one correspondence between representations of -\(\mathfrak{g}\) and \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\)-modules. It is usual -practice to write simply \(X \cdot v\) or \(X v\) for \(\rho(X) v\) when the -map \(\rho\) is clear from the context. For instance, one might say\dots +It is usual practice to write simply \(X \cdot v\) or \(X v\) for \(\rho(X) v\) +when the map \(\rho\) is clear from the context. For instance, one might +say\dots \begin{example}\label{ex:sl2-polynomial-rep} The space \(K[x, y]\) is a representation of \(\mathfrak{sl}_2(K)\) with @@ -824,7 +826,7 @@ map \(\rho\) is clear from the context. For instance, one might say\dots \begin{example} Given a Lie algebra \(\mathfrak{g}\) and \(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules \(V\) and - \(W\), the the spaces \(V \oplus W\), \(V^*\), \(V \otimes W\) and + \(W\), the spaces \(V \oplus W\), \(V^*\), \(V \otimes W\) and \(\operatorname{Hom}(V, W)\) are all \(\mathfrak{g}\)-modules -- where the action of \(\mathfrak{g}\) is given by \begin{align*} @@ -853,7 +855,7 @@ representations. \end{center} commutes for all \(X \in \mathfrak{g}\). We denote the space of all intertwiners \(V \to W\) by \(\operatorname{Hom}_{\mathfrak{g}}(V, W)\) -- as - opposed the the space \(\operatorname{Hom}(V, W)\) of all \(K\)-linear maps + opposed the space \(\operatorname{Hom}(V, W)\) of all \(K\)-linear maps \(V \to W\). \end{definition} @@ -866,8 +868,7 @@ terms. \begin{proposition} There is a natural equivalence of categories \(\mathfrak{g}\text{-}\mathbf{Mod} \isoto - \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\text{-}\mathbf{Mod}\), which takes - finite-dimensional representations to finitely generated modules. + \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\text{-}\mathbf{Mod}\). \end{proposition} \begin{proof} @@ -877,9 +878,7 @@ terms. \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\)-module structures for \(V\) -- i.e. homomorphisms \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g}) \to \operatorname{End}(V)\). This gives us a map that takes objects in \(\mathfrak{g}\text{-}\mathbf{Mod}\) to - objects in \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\text{-}\mathbf{Mod}\). This map - preserves the dimension of the representations, so it takes - finite-dimensional representations to finitely generated modules. + objects in \(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\text{-}\mathbf{Mod}\). As for the corresponding maps \(\operatorname{Hom}_{\mathfrak{g}}(V, W) \to \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})}(V, W)\), it suffices to note