- Commit
- 1b8026a4577ff005fec4e6564d12b4fafd89ee02
- Parent
- 212b52e177249cbc5364df41d0674b4ad9cbb6ec
- Author
- Pablo <pablo-escobar@riseup.net>
- Date
Started to work on hydrating the final chapter
Also fixed some minor typos
Source code for my notes on representations of semisimple Lie algebras and Olivier Mathieu's classification of simple weight modules
Started to work on hydrating the final chapter
Also fixed some minor typos
2 files changed, 106 insertions, 38 deletions
Status | File Name | N° Changes | Insertions | Deletions |
Modified | sections/coherent-families.tex | 140 | 104 | 36 |
Modified | sections/simple-weight.tex | 4 | 2 | 2 |
diff --git a/sections/coherent-families.tex b/sections/coherent-families.tex @@ -1,5 +1,7 @@ \chapter{Classification of Coherent Families} +% TODO: Write an introduction + % TODOOO: Is this decomposition unique?? \begin{proposition} Suppose \(\mathfrak{g} = \mathfrak{s}_1 \oplus \cdots \oplus \mathfrak{s}_r\) @@ -20,8 +22,8 @@ Example~\ref{thm:simple-weight-mod-is-tensor-prod}, there exists (unique) simple weight \(\mathfrak{s}_i\)-modules \(M_i\) such that \(M \cong M_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes M_r\). Take \(\mathcal{M}_i = \mExt(M_i)\). We will - show that \(\mathcal{M}_1 \otimes \cdots \mathcal{M}_r\) is a coherent - extension of \(M\). + show that \(\mathcal{M}_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes \mathcal{M}_r\) is a + coherent extension of \(M\). It is clear that \(\mathcal{M}_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes \mathcal{M}_r\) is a degree \(d\) bounded \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module containing \(M\) as a submodule. @@ -39,7 +41,8 @@ \end{align*} is polynomial, notice that the natural isomorphism of algebras \begin{align*} - f : \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{s}_1) \otimes \cdots \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{s}_1) + f : \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{s}_1) \otimes + \cdots \otimes \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{s}_1) & \isoto \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g}) \\ u_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes u_r & \mapsto u_1 \cdots u_r \end{align*} @@ -95,15 +98,16 @@ \(\mathcal{M} \cong \mathcal{M}_1 \otimes \cdots \otimes \mathcal{M}_r\). \end{proof} -% TODO: Rework this -In addition, it turns out that very few simple Lie algebras admit cuspidal -modules at all. Specifically\dots +This last result allows us to concentrate on focus exclusive on classifying +coherent \(\mathfrak{s}\)-families for the simple Lie algebras +\(\mathfrak{s}\). In addition, it turns out that very few simple algebras admit +irreducible coherent families at all. Namely\dots \begin{proposition}[Fernando]\label{thm:only-sl-n-sp-have-cuspidal} Let \(\mathfrak{s}\) be a finite-dimensional simple Lie algebra and suppose - there exists a cuspidal \(\mathfrak{s}\)-module. Then \(\mathfrak{s} \cong - \mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\) or \(\mathfrak{s} \cong \mathfrak{sp}_{2 n}(K)\) for - some \(n\). + there exists a infinite-dimensional cuspidal \(\mathfrak{s}\)-module. Then + \(\mathfrak{s} \cong \mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\) or \(\mathfrak{s} \cong + \mathfrak{sp}_{2 n}(K)\) for some \(n\). \end{proposition} \begin{corollary} @@ -113,33 +117,50 @@ modules at all. Specifically\dots \mathfrak{sp}_{2n}(K)\) for some \(n\). \end{corollary} -% TODO: Remove this: we will only focus on the combinatorial classification -% TODO: Simply notice that a more explicit "geometric" description of the -% cohorent families exists -Hence it suffices to classify the irreducible semisimple coherent families of -\(\mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\) and \(\mathfrak{sp}_{2 n}(K)\). These can be described -either algebraically, using combinatorial invariants -- which Mathieu does in -sections 7, 8 and 9 of his paper -- or geometrically, using algebraic varieties -and differential forms -- which is done in sections 11 and 12. While rather -complicated on its own, the geometric construction is more concrete than its -combinatorial counterpart. - -% TODO: Add some notes on the proof of this? -% I really don't think its worth proving this -\begin{proposition} +The problem of classifying the semisimple irreducible coherent +\(\mathfrak{g}\)-families for some arbitrary semisimple \(\mathfrak{g}\) can +thus be reduced to a proof by exaustion: it suffices to classify coherent +\(\mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\)-families and coherent +\(\mathfrak{sp}_{2n}(K)\)-families. We will follow this path by analysing each +case -- \(\mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\) and \(\mathfrak{sp}_{2n}(K)\) -- separately, +classifying coherent families in terms of combinatorial invariants -- as does +Mathieu in \cite[sec.~8,sec.~9]{mathieu}. Alternatively, Mathieu also provides +a more explicit ``geometric'' construction of the coherent families for both +\(\mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\) and \(\mathfrak{sp}_{2n}\) in sections 11 and 12 of his +paper. + +Before we proceed to the individual case analysis, however, we would like +discuss some further reductions to our general problem, the first of which is a +crutial refinement to Proposition~\ref{thm:coherent-families-are-all-ext} due +to Mathieu. + +\begin{proposition}\label{coh-family-is-ext-l-lambda} Let \(\mathcal{M}\) be a semisimple irreducible coherent \(\mathfrak{g}\)-family. Then there exists some \(\lambda \in \mathfrak{h}^*\) such that \(L(\lambda)\) is bounded and \(\mathcal{M} \cong \mExt(L(\lambda))\). \end{proposition} -% TODO: Finish this remark \begin{note} I once had the opportunity to ask Olivier Mathieu himself how he first came - across the notation of coherent families and what was the intuition behind - it. + across the notation of coherent families and what was his intuition behind + it. Unfortunately, his responce was that ``he did not remember.'' However, + Mathieu was able to tell me that ``the \emph{trick} is that I managed to show + that they all come from simple highest-weight modules, which were already + well understood.'' I personally find it likely that Mathieu first considered + the idea of twisting \(L(\lambda)\) -- for \(\lambda\) with \(L(\lambda)\) + bounded -- by a suitable automorphism \(\theta_\mu : \Sigma^{-1} + \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g}) \isoto \Sigma^{-1} \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\), as + in the proof of Proposition~\ref{thm:coh-ext-exists}, and only after decided + to agregate this data in a coherent family by summing over the \(Q\)-cosets + \(\mu + Q\), \(\mu \in \mathfrak{h}^*\). \end{note} +In case the significance of Proposition~\ref{coh-family-is-ext-l-lambda} is +unclear, the point is that it allows is to reduce the problem of classifying +the coherent \(\mathfrak{g}\)-families to that of aswering the following two +questions: + \begin{enumerate} \item When is \(L(\lambda)\) bounded? @@ -147,8 +168,33 @@ combinatorial counterpart. \(L(\mu)\) bounded, when is \(\mExt(L(\lambda)) \cong \mExt(L(\mu))\)? \end{enumerate} -% TODO: Explain beforehand why central characters exist and are unique -% TODO: Cite the discussion on central characters of [humphreys-cat-o] here +These are the questions which we will attempt to answer for \(\mathfrak{g} = +\mathfrak{sl}_n(K)\) and \(\mathfrak{g} = \mathfrak{sp}_{2n}(K)\). We begin by +providing a partial answer to the second answer by introducing an invariant of +coherent families, known as its \emph{central character}. + +To describe this invariant, we consider the Verma module \(M(\lambda) = +\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g}) \cdot m^+\). Given \(\mu \in \mathfrak{h}^*\) and \(m +\in M(\lambda)_\mu\), it is clear that \(u \cdot m \in M(\lambda)_\mu\) for all +central \(u \in \mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})\). In particular, \(u \cdot m^+ \in +M(\lambda)_\lambda = K m^+\) is a scalar multiple of \(m^+\) for all \(u \in +Z(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g}))\), say \(\chi_\lambda(u) m^+\) for some +\(\chi_\lambda(u) \in K\). More generally, if we take any \(m = v \cdot m^+ \in +M(\lambda)\) we can see that +\[ + u \cdot m + = v \cdot (u \cdot m^+) + = \chi_\lambda(u) \, v \cdot m^+ + = \chi_\lambda(u) m +\] + +Since every highest-weight module is a quotient of a Verma module, it follows +that \(u \in Z(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g}))\) acts on a highest-weight module +\(M\) of highest-weight \(\lambda\) via multiplication by \(\chi_\lambda(u)\). +In addition, it is clear that the function \(\chi_\lambda : +Z(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})) \to K\) must be an algebra homomorphism. This +leads us to the following definition. + \begin{definition} Given a highest weight \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module \(M\) of highest weight \(\lambda\), the unique algebra homomorphism \(\chi_\lambda : @@ -158,16 +204,20 @@ combinatorial counterpart. associated with the weight \(\lambda\)}. \end{definition} +Since a simple highest-weight \(\mathfrak{g}\)-module is uniquelly determined +by is highest-weight, it is clear that central characters are invariants of +simple highest-weight modules. We should point out that these are far from +perfect invariants, however. Namelly\dots + % TODO: Cite the definition of the dot action \begin{theorem}[Harish-Chandra] Given \(\lambda, \mu \in \mathfrak{h}^*\), \(\chi_\lambda = \chi_\mu\) if, - and only if \(\mu \in W \bullet \lambda\). All algebra homomorphism - \(Z(\mathcal{U}(\mathfrak{g})) \to K\) have the form \(\chi_\lambda\) for - some \(\lambda\). + and only if \(\mu \in W \bullet \lambda\). \end{theorem} -% TODO: Note we will prove that central characters are also invariants of -% coherent families +This and much more can be found in \cite[ch.~1]{humphreys-cat-o}. What is +interesting about all this to us is that, as it turns out, central character +are also invariants of coherent families. More specifically\dots \begin{proposition}\label{thm:coherent-family-has-uniq-central-char} Suppose \(\lambda, \mu \in \mathfrak{h}^*\) are such that \(L(\lambda)\) and @@ -197,9 +247,14 @@ combinatorial counterpart. \(\chi_\lambda(u) = \chi_\mu(u)\). \end{proof} -% TODO: Remark that the probability of σ_β ∙ λ ∈ P+ is slight: there precisely -% one element in the orbit of λ which is dominant integral, so the odds are -% 1/|W ∙ λ| +Central characters may thus be used to distinguished between two semisimple +irreducible coherent families. Unfortunately for us, as in the case of simple +highest-weight modules, central characters are not perfect invariants of +coherent families: there are non-isomorphic semisimple irreducible coherent +families which share a common central character. Nevertheless, Mathieu was able +to at least provide a somewhat \emph{precarious} version of the converse of +Proposition~\ref{thm:coherent-family-has-uniq-central-char}. Namelly\dots + \begin{lemma}\label{thm:lemma6.1} Let \(\beta \in \Sigma\) and \(\lambda \notin P^+\) be such that. \(L(\lambda)\) is bounded and \(\lambda(H_\beta) \notin \mathbb{N}\). Then @@ -209,6 +264,17 @@ combinatorial counterpart. \(\mExt(L(\sigma_\beta \bullet \lambda)) \cong \mExt(L(\lambda))\). \end{lemma} +\begin{note} + We should point out that, while it may very well be that \(\sigma_\beta + \bullet \lambda \in P^+\), there is generally only a slight chance of such an + event happening. Indeed, given \(\lambda \in \mathfrak{h}^*\), its orbit \(W + \bullet \lambda\) meets \(P^+\) precisely once, so that the probability of + \(\sigma_\beta \bullet \lambda \in P^+\) for some random \(\lambda \in + \mathfrak{h}^*\) is only \(\sfrac{1}{|W \bullet \lambda|}\). With the odds + stacked in our favor, we will later be able to exploit the second part of + Lemma~\ref{thm:lemma6.1} without much difficulty! +\end{note} + While technical in nature, this lemma already allows us to classify all semisimple irreducible coherent \(\mathfrak{sl}_2(K)\)-families. @@ -227,6 +293,8 @@ semisimple irreducible coherent \(\mathfrak{sl}_2(K)\)-families. - 2 \notin P^+\) then \(\mExt(L(\lambda)) \cong \mExt(L(- \lambda - 2))\). \end{example} +% TODO: Add a transition here + \section{Coherent \(\mathfrak{sp}_{2n}(K)\)-families} % TODO: Fix n >= 2
diff --git a/sections/simple-weight.tex b/sections/simple-weight.tex @@ -1471,7 +1471,7 @@ Explicitly\dots It should now be obvious\dots -\begin{proposition}[Mathieu] +\begin{proposition}[Mathieu]\label{thm:coh-ext-exists} There exists a coherent extension \(\mathcal{M}\) of \(M\). \end{proposition} @@ -1571,7 +1571,7 @@ Lo and behold\dots A sort of ``reciprocal'' of Theorem~\ref{thm:mathieu-ext-exists-unique} also holds. Namely\dots -\begin{proposition} +\begin{proposition}\label{thm:coherent-families-are-all-ext} Let \(\mathcal{M}\) be a semisimple irreducible coherent family and \(M \subset \mathcal{M}\) be an infinite-dimensional simple submodule. Then \(\mathcal{M} \cong \mExt(M)\). In particular, all semisimple coherent